Education & Pedagogy

Essentialism

Essentialism
Written by Arshad Yousafzai

Essentialism: The Enduring Essence, A Comprehensive Analysis of Essentialism from Plato to Postmodernity

Introduction: The Persistent Idea of Essence

Essentialism is the philosophical view that entities—be they objects, concepts, or living things—possess a set of attributes that are necessary to their identity and function. It is the belief in a “whatness” of things, an underlying, often immutable core that makes a thing the kind of thing that it is, and without which it would cease to be that thing. This seemingly straightforward proposition has echoed through Western thought for over two millennia, demonstrating a remarkable persistence and adaptability. Yet, the legacy of essentialism is one of profound duality. On one hand, it represents a foundational, perhaps even inescapable, tool of metaphysical inquiry and human cognition. It drives the fundamental philosophical question, “What is it?”, and provides a framework for understanding structure, identity, and definition in the world. On the other hand, when this same logic is turned from abstract objects to human beings, it has historically served as a powerful and pernicious instrument for social stratification, prejudice, and violence.

This report will navigate the deep chasm between these two faces of essentialism: essentialism as an ontological claim about the nature of reality, and essentialism as a psychological and ideological phenomenon—a way people intuitively categorize the world and a belief system used to justify social orders. The central intellectual task of this analysis is to trace the journey of this idea, from its origins in the abstract idealism of ancient Greece to its controversial applications in modern science, its role in shaping social identities and hierarchies, and its rejection by major currents of contemporary philosophy.

The report is structured in four parts. Part I will establish the core metaphysical framework of essentialism, exploring its genesis in Plato’s Theory of Forms and its grounding in physical reality through Aristotle’s concepts of substance and hylomorphism. Part II will examine how this philosophical doctrine was adopted, applied, and ultimately contested within the disciplines of biology, psychology, sociology, and education, revealing its controversial and often damaging impact. Part III will explore the great philosophical rejections of essentialism, focusing on the existentialist revolt, the critiques from social constructionism and nominalism, and the complex political maneuver of “strategic essentialism.” Finally, Part IV will address a distinct modern usage of the term to avoid confusion and will conclude by synthesizing the report’s findings on the enduring, complex, and deeply consequential legacy of the idea of essence.

Part I: The Philosophical Foundations of Essentialism

The intellectual architecture of essentialism was constructed in ancient Greece, primarily by Plato and his student, Aristotle. Though their systems differed profoundly, they together laid the groundwork for all subsequent discussions of essence, substance, and identity. They sought to answer fundamental questions about how we can know the world and what makes things what they are, and in doing so, they created a conceptual toolkit that would be used and abused for centuries to come.

Plato’s World of Forms: The Genesis of Essence

The origins of Western essentialism are inextricably linked to Plato and his celebrated Theory of Forms. Plato’s philosophy begins with a radical ontological division: the physical world we perceive through our senses is not the real world. It is a world of shadows, change, and decay, composed of imperfect facsimiles or copies of a higher, eternal, and unchanging reality—the world of the Forms or Ideas. These Forms are the perfect archetypes of everything that exists. For every kind of thing in our world, there is a corresponding perfect Form in this transcendent realm.

Plato’s essentialism emerged from a linguistic and conceptual puzzle: how is it that we can use a single, universal term, such as “bed,” to refer to a multitude of distinct, individual objects?. There are single beds, double beds, ornate beds, and simple beds, yet we recognize them all as belonging to the same category. Plato’s solution was that all these individual beds share something in common: they all “participate” in the single, perfect, and eternal Form of “Bed.” This participation grants them their “essential essence” of “bedness,” which is what makes them beds in the first place. The essence, therefore, is this abstract, ideal property that is intrinsic and a-contextual, defining the object’s true nature.

In dialogues such as the Timaeus, Plato provides a creation myth that further illuminates this concept. He describes a divine craftsperson, the Demiurge, who imposes order on a pre-existing chaos of matter. The Demiurge does this by looking to the eternal Forms as a blueprint or model, shaping the material world in their image. This establishes a powerful analogy between natural objects and human-made artifacts. Just as a carpenter builds a bed by referencing an idea or plan in their mind, the Demiurge forms the world by referencing the perfect Forms. In this model, the essence (the Form) precedes and determines the existence and identity of the physical object.

However, this elegant theory was not without its problems, some of which Plato himself recognized. In the dialogue Parmenides, he has the character of a young Socrates question the scope of the theory. If there is a perfect Form of Beauty and a perfect Form of Justice, must we also accept the existence of perfect Forms for mundane and even unpleasant things like “hair, mud, and dirt”?. This raises questions about the coherence and limits of the theory. More modern critiques, notably from the philosopher Karl Popper, have characterized Platonic essentialism as a form of “language worship”. This critique argues that Plato’s theory makes a grave error by pinning profound metaphysical significance onto what are merely linguistic labels. Humans invent words like “bed” as convenient labels to communicate about a class of objects. To then posit that this label corresponds to a real, eternal, metaphysical entity is to mistake a feature of our language for a feature of reality itself. This creates a paradox at the very heart of the essentialist project: the attempt to find objective truth through definition is based on the potentially fallacious assumption that our human-made definitions are windows into a pre-existing metaphysical order, rather than simply conventions we have created for our own purposes. This is a tension that will reappear throughout the history of essentialism.

Aristotle’s Substance and Hylomorphism: Grounding Essence in Reality

While Plato located essence in a transcendent world of Forms, his most famous student, Aristotle, brought it down to earth. Aristotle rejected the idea of a separate world of Forms, arguing instead that the essence of a thing is immanent, existing within the individual object itself. For Aristotle, the essence is what all members of a category have in common and what is necessary for their membership in that category. His classic example is that rationality is the essence of a human being; without rationality, a creature cannot be a human.

To explain this, Aristotle developed his theory of hylomorphism, which posits that every physical object is a composite of two principles: matter (hyle) and form (morphe). Matter is the “stuff” out of which a thing is made—the potentiality to become something. Form is the structure, the organizing principle, the essence that makes that stuff into a specific, actual thing. It is the form that gives a particular parcel of matter its identity, its “whatness” or

quiddity. A bronze statue, for example, is composed of matter (bronze) and form (the shape given to it by the sculptor). The form is its essence.

Central to Aristotle’s metaphysics is the concept of substance (ousia). A substance is a fundamental unit of reality, defined as a thing that exists independently and “in its own right”. This contrasts with properties or “accidents,” which can only exist “in” a substance. A smile, a wrinkle, or a color is are “ontological parasite”; they cannot exist apart from the thing that smiles, is wrinkled, or is colored. For Aristotle, the primary examples of substances are individual, concrete objects, particularly living organisms like a specific person or a specific horse. This focus on individual, tangible things stands in stark contrast to later philosophers like Spinoza, who argued for substance monism—the view that there is only one substance, the whole of reality, and that individual objects are merely modes of it.

This framework allowed Aristotle to make a crucial distinction that would become foundational to all subsequent essentialist thought: the distinction between essential and accidental properties.

  1. Essential Properties: These are the properties that make up a substance’s form or essence. A substance cannot lose an essential property without ceasing to be the kind of thing that it is. For Socrates, being human and being rational are essential properties. If he were to lose his rationality, he would cease to be Socrates.
  2. Accidental Properties: These are properties that a substance can gain or lose without changing its fundamental identity. Socrates can be sitting or standing, pale or tan, wise or foolish; these changes are alterations, but he remains the same substance, Socrates.

This seemingly abstract philosophical distinction provided the fundamental logical architecture for all later, more pernicious forms of social essentialism. The formal separation of properties into a hierarchy—the unchangeable and defining (essential) versus the changeable and superficial (accidental)—created a blueprint. Centuries later, this same logic would be applied to human subgroups. Socially constructed attributes like skin color or sex were elevated to the status of “essential” properties. Other human characteristics, such as intelligence, temperament, or moral worth, were then claimed to be causally determined by this supposed essence. In this way, a metaphysical tool designed to understand the identity of objects was transformed into an ideological weapon for defining, ranking, and ultimately oppressing human beings, framing social hierarchies not as contingent social arrangements but as the necessary and natural consequence of immutable essences.

Aristotle himself applied his essentialist framework in a normative context in his Nicomachean Ethics. Through his famous “function argument” (ergon), he sought to determine the ultimate good for human beings. He argues that for any type of thing that has a function (like a flautist or a sculptor), its good lies in performing that function well. He then asks what the unique function of a human being is. It is not mere life (which we share with plants) or perception (which we share with animals). The unique function of humans, their essence, is the activity of the soul by reason (logos). Therefore, the human good, or eudaimonia, is to live a life of rational activity performed with excellence. This argument provides a powerful example of how an essentialist account of human nature can be used to ground a system of ethics and define a good life.

Metaphysical Debates: Essence, Necessity, and Modality

The philosophical discussion of essentialism is deeply intertwined with the concepts of necessity and possibility, a field known as modal logic. A common way to formalize the idea of an essential property is through the language of possible worlds: a property is essential to an object if that object must have that property in every possible world in which it exists. Socrates is necessarily human; there is no possible world where the individual Socrates exists but is not a human.

This connection, however, became the basis for one of the most powerful critiques of essentialism in the 20th century, leveled by the philosopher W.V.O. Quine. Quine argued that essentialism confuses properties of language with properties of the world. His argument hinges on the distinction between

de re (about the thing) and de dicto (about the saying) modal claims. Consider the object that is the number.

  • The statement “Necessarily,  is greater than ” is true.
  • Now, consider that the number of planets in our solar system was, for a time, . The statement “Necessarily, the number of planets is greater than ” is false, because it is possible that there could have been only four planets.

Quine argued that the object is the same (the number ), but whether a property appears essential depends entirely on how we refer to it. From this, he concluded that it makes no sense to talk about an object having a property essentially (de re); we can only talk about the necessity of a statement (de dicto). For Quine and other anti-essentialists like Bertrand Russell, essentialism was a “metaphysical jungle” born from a linguistic confusion.

For decades, this critique was highly influential. However, essentialism was revived in the 1970s and 1980s by the work of philosophers Saul Kripke and Hilary Putnam. They argued powerfully for the existence of

de re necessity and real essences. Kripke argued that proper names (like “Socrates”) and natural kind terms (like “water” or “gold”) are “rigid designators”—they refer to the same individual or substance in every possible world. This allows us to make meaningful de re claims about them. They also argued for the existence of a posteriori necessities—truths that are necessary but can only be discovered through empirical investigation. The classic example is “Water is H₂O”. Before the discovery of its chemical composition, it was not known that water is H₂O. But now that we know, we understand that this is a necessary truth. Anything that is not H₂O is not water, no matter how much it looks or tastes like it. This implies that “water” has a real, underlying essence (its molecular structure) that we discovered, not invented.

This revival has led to a flourishing of contemporary work on essentialism. Philosopher Kit Fine, for instance, has argued for a non-modal conception of essence, suggesting that essence is more fundamental than necessity. In his view, we should not define essence in terms of necessity; rather, we should see metaphysical necessity as flowing from, and being explained by, the essences of things. These debates continue to shape contemporary metaphysics, demonstrating that the ancient questions first posed by Plato and Aristotle about the fundamental nature of reality remain as potent and contested as ever.

Part II: Essentialism in the Disciplines: Application and Controversy

While born in the abstract realm of metaphysics, the idea of essence proved to be a powerful and adaptable concept that was readily applied to more concrete domains of knowledge. In the sciences, psychology, sociology, and education, essentialist thinking has been used to structure theories, classify phenomena, and guide practice. However, in nearly every case, its application has been fraught with controversy, often acting as a barrier to scientific progress and a justification for social inequality.

The Biological Impasse: Species, Kinds, and Evolution

In the history of biology, essentialism played a central and ultimately obstructive role. Before Charles Darwin, the dominant approach to classifying life, known as typology, was deeply essentialist. Influenced by the Platonic and Aristotelian traditions, naturalists viewed species as fixed, discrete, and unchanging types. Each species was thought to be defined by a unique, underlying essence or “type,” and all members of that species were manifestations of this ideal form. The observable variation among individuals within a species—differences in size, color, or behavior—was largely dismissed as accidental “noise” or an imperfect reflection of the true, essential type. The job of the taxonomist was to look past this superficial variation to discern the defining, essential characters of the species.

Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection, published in 1859, represented a fundamental challenge to this static worldview. The very engine of evolution is variation. It is not noise to be ignored, but the essential raw material upon which natural selection acts to produce change over time. Darwin’s “population thinking” replaced the typological concept of a species. A species is not a fixed type but a dynamic population of unique individuals that collectively evolves. This created an irreconcilable conflict: classical essentialism sees the essence of a species as a permanent and unalterable property of each organism, while the theory of evolution demonstrates that the properties of a species are contingent and change over time at the population level. For a long time, the stranglehold of essentialist thinking was a significant barrier to the acceptance and understanding of evolution.

In the wake of the Darwinian revolution, many philosophers of biology concluded that essentialism was incompatible with modern biology. A prominent alternative, developed by Michael Ghiselin and David Hull, is the “species as individuals” thesis. This view argues that species are not “natural kinds” in the traditional essentialist sense (like the kind “gold”). Instead, they are vast, spatiotemporally extended historical entities. A species like

Homo sapiens is a particular lineage, a specific branch on the tree of life. Like a person or an individual nation-state, it has a beginning (speciation) and an end (extinction), and its parts are causally integrated. It is a particular thing, not a universal type.

Despite the dominance of this anti-essentialist view, some contemporary philosophers have attempted to formulate new versions of essentialism that might be compatible with evolutionary biology.

  • Historical Essentialism: Proposed by philosophers like Griffiths and LaPorte, this view relocates the essence of a species from its intrinsic properties (like morphology or genetics) to its relational properties. The essence of a biological taxon, on this account, is its unique historical origin—its specific position in the phylogenetic tree and its descent from a particular common ancestor. The essence is the lineage itself. This view has been criticized, however, because cladistics, the primary method for reconstructing evolutionary relationships, defines groups based on sister-group relations (shared ancestry) rather than being able to pinpoint the single, specific most recent ancestor required by the historical essentialist definition.
  • Homeostatic Property Cluster (HPC) Kinds: A more flexible approach was proposed by Richard Boyd. The HPC theory suggests that natural kinds, including biological species, are not defined by a set of necessary and sufficient properties. Instead, they are defined by a “cluster” of properties that reliably co-occur because of some underlying causal mechanism or set of mechanisms (a “homeostatic” process). For a species, these mechanisms could be gene flow, shared developmental constraints, or a common ecological niche. This model allows for variation, exceptions, and fuzzy boundaries, making it far more compatible with the realities of biology than classical essentialism.

This history reveals a deep contradiction in the role of essentialist thinking. In biology, the search for fixed, unchanging essences was a dogma that actively hindered scientific progress by obscuring the dynamic, variable nature of life. This stands in stark contrast to its application in other fields, such as education, where the identification of “essentials” is often framed as a virtue.

The Essentializing Mind: Psychological Essentialism as Cognitive Bias

Separate from the metaphysical question of whether essences truly exist is the psychological question of why humans seem so inclined to believe they do. “Psychological essentialism” is the term for this pervasive cognitive tendency to represent categories—especially natural kinds like animals and plants, but also social kinds—as having a deep, hidden, and causally powerful “essence” that makes them what they are.

Decades of research in developmental psychology, pioneered by Susan Gelman and others, have shown that this is not a learned philosophical position but an early-emerging and powerful cognitive bias. Parents do not explicitly teach their children to essentialize. Rather, preschool-aged children spontaneously construct concepts that reflect an essentialist stance. They intuitively believe that category membership is innate, stable over time, and predictive of a host of non-obvious properties. In classic studies, children insist that a raccoon surgically altered to look and act like a skunk is still, deep down, a raccoon, or that a calf raised by pigs will grow up to moo, not oink. This bias leads children to look beyond superficial appearances and search for a hidden, underlying reality, challenging the older view of children as purely concrete thinkers. This cognitive tendency likely functions as a powerful heuristic or mental shortcut. In a complex world, it allows us to simplify information, make strong inductive inferences, and form predictions based on the belief that a category label points to a rich, underlying causal structure.

This essentializing tendency extends powerfully into the moral domain. “Moral essentialism” is the belief that moral traits like “good” and “bad” are not just descriptions of behavior but are stable, innate essences that define a person’s core identity. Research shows that even young children essentialize moral character, often believing that a “bad” person is fundamentally and unchangeably bad. This has profound social consequences:

  • Punitive Responses: The belief that negative moral character is a fixed, internal essence is strongly linked to more punitive attitudes. If misbehavior stems from an unchangeable “badness,” then rehabilitation seems futile and punishment seems more appropriate. This is evident in the legal system, where concepts like “three strikes” laws and permanent felon disenfranchisement reflect a focus on punishing a perceived “bad character” rather than just a specific act. It is also seen in schools, where teachers who attribute misbehavior to a student’s internal disposition (seeing them as a “troublemaker”) respond more punitively, a dynamic that contributes to the disproportionate disciplining of minority students.
  • Prosocial Behavior: Moral essentialism also influences how we help and praise others. Using noun labels that imply an essence (e.g., telling a child to “be a helper” instead of just “to help”) can be a powerful motivator for prosocial behavior. However, this can backfire. If a child who is told they “are a helper” fails at a task, it can lead to negative feelings, as the failure is perceived as a reflection on their core self, not just their actions.

The Social Matrix: Gender, Race, and Cultural Essentialism

The most devastating application of essentialist logic has been to human social groups. Social essentialism involves taking fluid, complex, and often socially constructed categories like race, gender, and culture, and treating them as if they were fixed, discrete, and biologically determined natural kinds. This cognitive move provides a powerful ideological justification for prejudice, discrimination, and social hierarchy.

The pathway from an innate cognitive bias to systemic social injustice is direct and demonstrable. The human mind appears predisposed to simplify the world by seeking essences. When this cognitive tool is applied to social categories that are already imbued with power dynamics and historical prejudice, it allows people to perceive those social arrangements as natural and inevitable. The belief that social differences stem from deep, immutable essences makes inequality seem logical and discrimination seem justified. Thus, social injustice is not merely a product of political or economic factors; it is powerfully reinforced by a fundamental feature of human cognition, making it incredibly resilient and difficult to dismantle.

  • Racial Essentialism: This is the belief that human races are distinct biological groups, and that this biological essence determines not only physical traits but also intelligence, personality, culture, and moral worth. This ideology was systematically developed during the European colonial period, with intellectual contributions from Enlightenment philosophers like David Hume and Immanuel Kant, to create a “scientific” rationale for slavery, imperial conquest, and the subjugation of non-European peoples. By defining racialized others as possessing an inferior essence, colonial powers could justify dehumanization and exploitation. Today, psychological research confirms that holding essentialist views about race is strongly correlated with higher levels of racial prejudice and diminished empathy for members of other racial groups.
  • Gender Essentialism: This is the belief that men and women possess fixed, universal, and biologically determined essences that dictate their psychology, abilities, and proper social roles. It promotes stereotypes such as the idea that women are inherently nurturing, emotional, and supportive, while men are inherently aggressive, independent, and competitive. Feminist theory has long identified gender essentialism as a cornerstone of patriarchy. It functions to limit human potential by trapping both men and women in rigid stereotypes, and it rationalizes gender inequality by presenting socially imposed roles as natural and immutable.
  • Cultural Essentialism: This form of essentialism involves attributing a fixed, homogeneous essence to all members of a particular culture or nationality, leading to stereotypes like “All Asians are good at math” or “All Italians are passionate”. It dangerously misrepresents culture, which is a dynamic, contested, and constantly negotiated set of practices and beliefs, as a static and “imprisoning cocoon”. This oversimplification erases the vast diversity within cultures and fuels prejudice and misunderstanding between them.

The Essentialist Classroom: Debates in the Philosophy of Education

In the field of education, essentialism refers to a specific and influential pedagogical philosophy. Pioneered in the 1930s by American educator William Bagley, educational essentialism is a teacher-centered approach that argues for a curriculum grounded in a common core of “essential” knowledge, skills, and traditional moral values. The philosophy emphasizes academic rigor, discipline, and the mastery of foundational subjects such as mathematics, natural science, history, foreign languages, and literature, while often frowning upon vocational courses.

The primary goal of educational essentialism is to transmit the core cultural heritage and intellectual traditions of a society to the next generation, thereby creating knowledgeable, disciplined, and well-balanced citizens capable of contributing to a democracy. In this model, the teacher serves as an intellectual and moral authority, responsible for imparting this essential knowledge and instilling values like respect for authority, perseverance, and duty. Student progress is typically evaluated through standardized achievement tests.

This educational philosophy is not without its vocal critics. Opponents argue that its rigid, one-size-fits-all approach can stifle students’ creativity, curiosity, and critical thinking skills by prioritizing rote memorization over inquiry-based learning. By focusing narrowly on a traditional canon, it may limit students’ exposure to diverse cultures, perspectives, and interdisciplinary ways of thinking. Furthermore, its emphasis on standardization is seen as potentially ignoring the diverse learning styles, abilities, and individual needs of students. Essentialism in education is often positioned in direct contrast to more student-centered philosophies like progressivism (which emphasizes learning by doing) and constructivism (which emphasizes that students actively construct their own knowledge). The debate between these philosophies continues to shape discussions about curriculum design, teaching methods, and the ultimate purpose of schooling.

Part III: The Great Rejection: Critiques and Alternatives

As essentialism’s influence spread from metaphysics to social and political thought, it generated powerful philosophical counter-movements. The 20th century, in particular, saw a profound rejection of essentialist ideas about human nature and identity from several influential schools of thought. These critiques challenged the very notion of a fixed, predetermined self, offering instead visions of identity as fluid, created, or socially constructed.

The Existentialist Revolt: “Existence Precedes Essence”

Perhaps the most direct and famous assault on essentialism came from the existentialist philosophers. Jean-Paul Sartre, in a radical inversion of the classical formula, declared that for human beings, “existence precedes essence”. This became the central tenet of atheistic existentialism.

What this means is that, unlike a manufactured object like a paper-knife, whose essence (its design, purpose, and definition) is conceived by its creator before it is made, human beings have no such pre-determined blueprint. We are first simply thrown into the world—we exist. It is only after we exist, through the sum of our choices and actions, that we define ourselves and create our essence, our nature. There is no universal, eternal, or unchangeable “human nature” that dictates who we are or what we must become.

This leads to the core existentialist themes of radical freedom and profound responsibility. With no divine creator and no fixed essence, humans are “condemned to be free”. We are entirely responsible for creating our values and giving meaning to our own lives in what is an otherwise meaningless and absurd universe. To live authentically, from an existentialist perspective, is to embrace this terrifying freedom and to consciously forge an identity based on one’s own critically examined choices. The opposite of authenticity is “bad faith” (

mauvaise foi), a form of self-deception where one flees from this freedom by pretending to be a determined object, acting as if one’s role, character, or identity were fixed and unchangeable, dictated by society, biology, or some other external force. Thinkers across the existentialist spectrum, from Søren Kierkegaard to Martin Heidegger and Simone de Beauvoir, shared this fundamental rejection of an essentialist conception of the human being.

The Social Constructionist and Nominalist Critique

While existentialism focused on individual freedom, another powerful critique emerged from a focus on social forces. Social constructionism is the view that many of the categories we take for granted as being “natural” or “real” are, in fact, products of specific social, cultural, and historical processes. This is especially true for social categories like gender, race, and sexuality.

A foundational text for this perspective is Simone de Beauvoir’s The Second Sex, in which she famously wrote, “One is not born, but rather, becomes a woman”. This statement encapsulates the constructionist critique of gender essentialism. It argues that “femininity” is not a biological or natural essence that flows from female anatomy. Rather, it is a complex set of behaviors, expectations, and social roles that are imposed upon individuals from birth by a patriarchal society. Social constructionism does not deny the reality of biological differences, nor does it deny the very real consequences that these social categories have on people’s lives. What it denies is that these categories are natural, inevitable, or based on any underlying essence. They are constructs, built and maintained through language, power structures, and social practices.

A deeper and more fundamental metaphysical critique comes from nominalism. Nominalism is the philosophical position that universal concepts—like “humanity,” “redness,” or “justice”—do not correspond to any real, independently existing entities or essences. They are simply names (nomina) or mental labels that we use for convenience to group individual things that resemble each other. Nominalism is a direct rejection of Platonic realism and its world of Forms. It argues that only particulars exist; universals or essences are constructs of the mind or language, not features of reality itself. The nominalist position is often defended on the principle of parsimony, or Ockham’s Razor, which states that one should not multiply entities beyond necessity. Positing a whole realm of abstract essences is seen as a violation of this principle. From a nominalist perspective, the entire essentialist project is based on a category mistake: it searches for a real-world basis for what are ultimately just our own linguistic and mental conventions.

Strategic Essentialism: A Political Reappropriation

In the late 20th century, a more nuanced and politically motivated engagement with essentialism emerged from postcolonial theory. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak introduced the concept of “strategic essentialism”. This is not a metaphysical claim about the nature of reality, but a description of a political tactic.

Strategic essentialism refers to the conscious and temporary decision by a marginalized or subaltern group to adopt a simplified, unified, and “essentialized” identity to act collectively and achieve specific political goals. Spivak and others recognized that while essentialism is theoretically flawed and often politically dangerous, as it can erase internal differences and reinforce stereotypes, it can be a necessary strategy in a world structured by power. For a marginalized group to be heard by a dominant culture, it may need to “speak” with a single, unified voice, temporarily setting aside internal complexities and debates. For example, diverse groups of people may mobilize under the single banner of “women” or a specific ethnic identity to fight for civil rights or resist colonial narratives.

However, Spivak was keenly aware of the risks involved. The primary danger is that the temporary strategy becomes a permanent reality; the politically useful fiction becomes a rigid, exclusionary dogma. The very stereotypes that the group is trying to combat can become internalized and reinforced. In her later work, Spivak expressed deep dissatisfaction with how the concept had been co-opted by nationalist and other movements to promote a non-strategic, genuine essentialism, and she effectively disavowed the term due to its misuse. Strategic essentialism thus remains a highly contested concept, highlighting the complex and often paradoxical relationship between identity, politics, and theory.

Philosophical StanceView on EssenceView on Identity/Human NatureKey Proponents/Thinkers
Metaphysical EssentialismExists independently of the mind; a real, defining property of an object or kind.Predetermined by an inherent, unchanging nature or set of properties (e.g., rationality).Plato, Aristotle, Kripke
ExistentialismDoes not pre-exist; it is created by the individual through choices and actions.Radically free; “existence precedes essence.” Individuals create their own nature.Sartre, de Beauvoir, Kierkegaard
Social ConstructionismDoes not exist in nature for social categories; it is a product of social, cultural, and historical processes.Fluid and constructed through social interaction, language, and power structures.Butler, Foucault, de Beauvoir
NominalismDoes not exist as a real property; it is a mental or linguistic construct (a “name”).Categories used to define identity are conventions, not reflections of an underlying reality.(Historically) Roscellinus, Ockham; (Modern) Quine

Part IV: Essentialism in the 21st Century

As this report has demonstrated, essentialism is a concept with a long, complex, and often contentious history in philosophy, science, and social theory. In the 21st century, however, the term has been adopted in a completely different context: the world of lifestyle design and productivity. This modern usage, popularized by author Greg McKeown, shares a name with the philosophical doctrine but little else. To provide a truly comprehensive analysis, it is crucial to explicitly disambiguate these two concepts to avoid confusion.

The Other Essentialism: Greg McKeown and the Pursuit of Less

In his bestselling 2014 book, Essentialism: The Disciplined Pursuit of Less, Greg McKeown introduced a new meaning for an old word. This “lifestyle essentialism” is not a metaphysical theory about the nature of reality, but a practical and systematic discipline for personal and professional effectiveness. It is a direct response to the modern feeling of being overworked, overstretched, and overwhelmed—of being busy but not productive.

The core philosophy of McKeown’s essentialism is the rejection of the idea that we can or should try to “do it all.” Instead, it advocates for a disciplined and deliberate approach to life based on three core principles :

  1. Discern: The first step is to explore one’s options and deliberately distinguish the “vital few” from the “trivial many”. This requires space to think, clarity of purpose, and the application of highly selective criteria to choices. An essentialist constantly asks, “Is this the most important thing I should be doing with my time and resources right now?”
  2. Eliminate: Once the non-essentials have been identified, the next step is to actively eliminate them. This is often the most difficult part, as it requires the courage to say “no” gracefully to requests, to uncommit from sunk costs, and to set clear boundaries.
  3. Execute: With the clutter of non-essentials removed, the final step is to create a system that makes executing on the vital few things almost effortless. This involves building routines, preparing for obstacles with buffers, and focusing on small, consistent progress.

The goal of this lifestyle strategy is not simply to do less for the sake of doing less, but to get the right things done. It is about making the wisest possible investment of one’s time and energy in order to operate at one’s “highest point of contribution,” leading to a life of greater success, meaning, and fulfillment.

The connection between McKeown’s concept and the philosophical tradition is purely semantic; they are homonyms that address fundamentally different questions. Lifestyle essentialism is about identifying what is subjectively important or valuable to an individual based on their personal goals. Philosophical essentialism is about identifying what is metaphysically necessary for an entity’s identity, independent of anyone’s values or goals. The following table makes this distinction clear.

FeaturePhilosophical EssentialismLifestyle Essentialism (Greg McKeown)
DomainMetaphysics, OntologyProductivity, Lifestyle Design, Business Strategy
Core QuestionWhat makes a thing what it is?What is most important for me to do?
Nature of “Essential”A necessary, inherent, unchanging property that defines identity.A personally-defined priority; the most valuable use of one’s time and energy.
GoalTo understand the fundamental structure of reality.To achieve greater focus, productivity, and fulfillment by doing less, but better.
Key ThinkersPlato, Aristotle, KripkeGreg McKeown

Synthesis and Conclusion: The Legacy of an Idea

This report has traced the long and winding path of essentialism, from its origins as a solution to metaphysical puzzles in ancient Greece to its applications and rejections in science, society, and contemporary life. In conclusion, we must return to the concept’s profound and challenging duality.

On one hand, essentialism appears to be a fundamental, perhaps even inescapable, feature of human thought. The drive to categorize, to define, and to seek underlying causes is deeply embedded in our cognition. The Socratic question that arguably began Western philosophy—”What is X?”—is, at its heart, an essentialist question. It presumes that there is a stable, definable answer to be found. Psychological research suggests that this mode of thinking is not a sophisticated philosophical stance but a cognitive default, an intuitive bias that emerges spontaneously in early childhood and helps us make sense of a complex world. In this sense, we may all be natural-born essentialists.

On the other hand, the legacy of this idea is a stark and brutal cautionary tale. When the intellectual framework for defining the essence of a triangle is applied to defining the essence of a human being, the consequences can be catastrophic. The history of racial, gender, and cultural essentialism is a history of prejudice, oppression, and violence, all rationalized by the claim that social hierarchies are merely reflections of a natural, essential order. A concept developed to bring clarity and understanding to the world became a tool to justify its most profound injustices.

The primary ethical and intellectual challenge posed by essentialism, then, is not the task of eliminating it from our thinking—a feat that may well be impossible. Rather, the challenge is to cultivate a critical awareness of where, how, and why we apply it. The search for essence reflects a deep human desire for order, stability, and meaning. But the history of essentialism demonstrates with painful clarity the immense moral responsibility that comes with the power to define the world and, most importantly, the people who inhabit it.

References 

  1. Essentialism – Wikipedia, accessed June 13, 2025, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Essentialism
  2. Essentialism – Queer Cultures 101 – ScholarBlogs, accessed June 13, 2025, https://scholarblogs.emory.edu/queercultures101/2023/10/27/essentialism/
  3. What’s is Essentialism – plato – Philosophy Stack Exchange, accessed June 13, 2025, https://philosophy.stackexchange.com/questions/77963/what-s-is-essentialism
  4. Essentialism: The Logical Fallacy Plaguing Us Since Plato – New Discourses, accessed June 13, 2025, https://newdiscourses.com/2021/02/essentialism-logical-fallacy-plaguing-us-since-plato/
  5. Being, Essence and Substance in Plato and Aristotle – Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, accessed June 13, 2025, https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/being-essence-and-substance-in-plato-and-aristotle/
  6. Essentialism | Moral Realism, Metaphysics & Epistemology | Britannica, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.britannica.com/topic/essentialism-philosophy
  7. What’s the difference between metaphysical monism and essentialism? : r/askphilosophy, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.reddit.com/r/askphilosophy/comments/1ghlak/whats_the_difference_between_metaphysical_monism/
  8. Essentialism in Aristotle – University of Washington, accessed June 13, 2025, https://faculty.washington.edu/smcohen/EssentialismAristotle.pdf
  9. Essentialism and Pluralism in Aristotle’s ‘Function Argument’ (NE 1.7), accessed June 13, 2025, https://scholar.harvard.edu/files/abolafia/files/09-abolafia.pdf
  10. Critiques of Essentialism? : r/philosophy – Reddit, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.reddit.com/r/philosophy/comments/w8oru/critiques_of_essentialism/
  11. Kinds and Essences: Rescuing the New Biological Essentialism, accessed June 13, 2025, https://diposit.ub.edu/dspace/bitstream/2445/198442/1/Kortabarria_Kinds_and_Essences_Rescuing_the_New_Biological_Essentialism.pdf
  12. Essence and Essentialism – Bibliography – PhilPapers, accessed June 13, 2025, https://philpapers.org/browse/essence-and-essentialism
  13. Essentialism in Biology – PhilPapers, accessed June 13, 2025, https://philpapers.org/archive/WILEIB.docx
  14. Concept of species essentialist | Frozen Evolution. Or, that’s not the …, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.frozenevolution.com/concept-species-essentialist
  15. Essentialism, History, and Biological Taxa, accessed June 13, 2025, https://arts.ucalgary.ca/sites/default/files/teams/33/Graduate%20Documents/makmiller_pedrosos_2010_essay-competition_0.pdf
  16. Psychological Essentialism and Natural Kinds – PhilArchive, accessed June 13, 2025, https://philarchive.org/archive/MARPEA-26v1
  17. Psychological Essentialism | Psychologs Magazine | Mental Health Magazine | Psychology Magazine | Self-Help Magazine, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.psychologs.com/psychological-essentialism/
  18. The Essential Child: Origins of Essentialism in Everyday Thought | Request PDF, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.researchgate.net/publication/247868542_The_Essential_Child_Origins_of_Essentialism_in_Everyday_Thought
  19. The Essential Child: Origins of Essentialism in Everyday Thought …, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.amazon.com/Essential-Child-Essentialism-Cognitive-Development/dp/0195181980
  20. The development and developmental consequences of social …, accessed June 13, 2025, https://pmc.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/articles/PMC5591057/
  21. Essentialist animals? – International Cognition and Culture Institute, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.cognitionandculture.net/blogs/helen-de-cruzs-blog/essentialist-animals/index.html
  22. Essentialism bias | Shortcuts, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.shortcogs.com/bias/essentialism-bias
  23. The development and consequences of moral essentialism, accessed June 13, 2025, https://columbiasamclab.weebly.com/uploads/5/9/0/6/59061709/heiphetz_2020_advances_in_child_dev_and_beh.pdf
  24. Essentialism vs. Non-Essentialism: Understanding Identity Through a Dynamic Lens – Teacher’s Notes, accessed June 13, 2025, https://teachersnotes.net/2025/03/04/essentialism-vs-non-essentialism-understanding-identity-through-a-dynamic-lens/
  25. Gender Essentialism Predicts Prejudice against Gender Nonconformity in Two Cultural Contexts – PMC, accessed June 13, 2025, https://pmc.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/articles/PMC11086985/
  26. Constructionist Vs Essentialist Feminism – The Student Theorist: An …, accessed June 13, 2025, https://pressbooks.pub/opentheoryhandbook/chapter/constructionist-vs-essentialist-feminism/
  27. What’s wrong with essentialism? – CORE, accessed June 13, 2025, https://core.ac.uk/download/pdf/216427.pdf
  28. ED593579 – Essentialism in Philosophy, Psychology, Education, Social and Scientific Scopes, Online Submission, 2018 – ERIC, accessed June 13, 2025, https://eric.ed.gov/?id=ED593579
  29. Analysis of Essentialism: The Educational Philosophy – Gavin Publishers, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.gavinpublishers.com/article/view/analysis-of-essentialism-the-educational-philosophy-
  30. Essentialism – SIUE, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.siue.edu/~ptheodo/foundations/essentialism.html
  31. Essentialism and Perennialism | EBSCO Research Starters, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.ebsco.com/research-starters/religion-and-philosophy/essentialism-and-perennialism
  32. essentialism in philosophy, psychology, education, social and – ERIC, accessed June 13, 2025, https://files.eric.ed.gov/fulltext/ED593579.pdf
  33. Essentialism in Educational Philosophy – Sparx Services, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.sparxservices.org/blog/essentialism-in-educational-philosophy
  34. Thoughts on Teaching: Constructivism, Essentialism, and Mastery, accessed June 13, 2025, https://classicalacademicpress.com/blogs/novare-science/thoughts-on-teaching-constructivism-essentialism-and-mastery
  35. Existentialism vs. Essentialism – (Intro to Humanities) – Vocab …, accessed June 13, 2025, https://library.fiveable.me/key-terms/introduction-humanities/existentialism-vs-essentialism
  36. To grasp existentialism, start with essentialism. – Reddit, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.reddit.com/r/Existentialism/comments/18n7mku/to_grasp_existentialism_start_with_essentialism/
  37. Giving Life Meaning: Existentialism vs. Essentialism – Her Campus, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.hercampus.com/school/cwu/giving-life-meaning-existentialism-vs-essentialism/
  38. Existentialism vs Essentialism: A Comparative Study – MAY CONTAIN PHILOSOPHY, accessed June 13, 2025, https://maycontainphilosophy.com/existentialism-vs-essentialism/
  39. “Essentialist and Existentialist: Two Visions of Authenticity” by Colin …, accessed June 13, 2025, https://ecommons.udayton.edu/graduate_theses/6771/
  40. Identity and Meaning: Contrasts of Existentialist and Essentialist …, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.meaning.ca/web/wp-content/uploads/2019/10/200-13-397-2-10-20171212.pdf
  41. Essentialism and Social Constructionism : r/askphilosophy – Reddit, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.reddit.com/r/askphilosophy/comments/au24oq/essentialism_and_social_constructionism/
  42. pressbooks.pub, accessed June 13, 2025, https://pressbooks.pub/opentheoryhandbook/chapter/constructionist-vs-essentialist-feminism/#:~:text=Simply%20put%2C%20essentialist%20feminism%20argues,conditioning%20orchestrated%20by%20the%20patriarchy.
  43. www.researchgate.net, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.researchgate.net/publication/319573060_Essentialism_versus_Nominalism#:~:text=Essentialism%20is%20the%20philosophical%20position,reflect%20social%20and%20linguistic%20conventions.
  44. essentialism v nominalism : r/askphilosophy – Reddit, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.reddit.com/r/askphilosophy/comments/90tyl8/essentialism_v_nominalism/
  45. Essentialism versus Nominalism | Request PDF – ResearchGate, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.researchgate.net/publication/319573060_Essentialism_versus_Nominalism
  46. Strategic essentialism – Wikipedia, accessed June 13, 2025, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Strategic_essentialism
  47. Gayatri Spivak’s Strategic Essentialism: Meaning & Examples – Literature and Criticism, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.literatureandcriticism.com/strategic-essentialism/
  48. Spivakian Study of Strategic Essentialism in the Autumn of the Patriarch and Waiting for the Barbarians in Post-colonial Literature, accessed June 13, 2025, https://iaiest.com/iaj/index.php/IAJSS/article/download/IAJSS1510042/1169/1133
  49. Decoding Strategic Essentialism – Number Analytics, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.numberanalytics.com/blog/strategic-essentialism-culture-colonialism
  50. Essentialism by Greg McKeown: Book Summary | Runn, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.runn.io/blog/essentialism-summary
  51. I followed the rules of essentialism and it changed my life | The …, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.independent.co.uk/health-and-fitness/essentialism-changed-my-life-b2731188.html
  52. Essentialism: The Disciplined Pursuit of Less: McKeown, Greg: 9780804137409 – Amazon.com, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.amazon.com/Essentialism-Disciplined-Pursuit-Greg-McKeown/dp/0804137404
  53. Summary of Essentialism by Greg McKeown – Thrive Street Advisors, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.thrivestreetadvisors.com/leadership-library/essentialism
  54. Book Summary: Essentialism by Greg McKeown | Sam Thomas Davies, accessed June 13, 2025, https://www.samuelthomasdavies.com/book-summaries/business/essentialism/
  55. So… what does Essentialism mean in a lifestyle context? Simplejoy …, accessed June 13, 2025, https://simplejoy.co.uk/2016/08/08/essentialism/

4 Comments

Leave a Comment